The gravitational field manifests itself in the motion of bodies.
- Einstein and Infeld (1949, p. 209)
Abstract
I argue that the best interpretation of the general theory of relativity (GTR) has need of a causal entity (i.e., the gravitational field), and causal structure that is not reducible to light cone structure. I suggest that this causal interpretation of GTR helps defeat a key premise in one of the most popular arguments for causal reductionism, viz., the argument from physics.
Similar content being viewed by others
Notes
For more discussion of these types of cases see Paul and Hall (2013).
This type of counter-example to the counterfactual theory is discussed by Paul (2009, pp. 177–182).
The opening page of The Oxford Handbook of Causation (OHC) suggests as much (Beebee et al. 2009, p. 1). But see also the remarks in Carroll (2009), Paul and Hall (2013, p. 249), Psillos (2009, p. 154), Schaffer (2007, pp. 872–874) and Tooley (1987, p. 5), inter alios. Carroll (2009, p. 285) notes that the OHC is filled with papers by reductionists who tell the many stories of failure. Schaffer (2007, pp. 872–874) pleads with his fellow reductionists to abandon the pursuit of reductively analyzing the causal relation. He (2016, Sect. 2.1) believes that the argument from physics is what shows that causal reductionism is true. Douglas Kutach (2013, pp. 282–306) tries to show that there probably is no “complete and consistent systematization of cause-effect relations ‘out there in reality’ that correspond to our folk concept of causation…” (ibid., p. 282) gesturing at the well-known problems and counter-examples to unified theories.
Schaffer (2008, p. 92). The argument Schaffer develops is explicitly one for causal reductionism and not causal eliminativism (cf. ibid., pp. 82–83, p. 86, p. 92). Causal eliminativism is the view that there are no obtaining causal relations (see Russell 1912–1913).
Schaffer’s original argument appealed to scientific practice in general. It is clear, however, that he privileges physics as that science which puts us in touch with the fundamental. Thus, if physics has no need of causation, causal reductionism is well evidenced.
For other arguments in favor of causal reductionism, see Norton (2007a, b). Cf. the recent critical discussion in Frisch (2014, pp. 1–21).
Cartwright (1993, p. 426).
See Craig (2001, 2008, p. 11). Though Frisch (2005, p. 3) does not affirm that the formalism/interpretation distinction is a part of the correct view of theory structure, he calls something like the view I defend the “standard conception”.
I will be applying the standard conception to general relativity, but in so doing I do not mean to enter the debate between Curiel (2009)—who argues that GTR does not need an interpretation—on one side, and Belot (1996) and Rovelli (1999)—who argue that GTR does require an interpretation—on the other. This is because the conception of interpretation in that debate is much broader than what is intended in the present study.
The notion of physical interpretation (the standard conception) I have in mind is closer to Curiel’s (2009, p. 46) idea of a categorical interpretation, and it seems almost obvious to me that GTR sits in need of an interpretation in that sense. Indeed, Curiel himself remarked, “…all physical theories have known interpretative problems of the categorical sort…” Curiel (2009, p. 47) emphasis in the original.
My approach to physical interpretations is completely consistent with both the syntactical and semantic views of scientific theory structure. For the syntactic view I have in mind, see Carnap (1967), Hempel (1965, pp. 173–226); and the critical discussion in Suppe (1989, pp. 38–77). Sometimes the syntactic view is called “the received view”. On the semantic view, see Giere (1988), Suppe (1989), van Fraassen (1970), (1991, pp. 4–8), (2008, pp. 309–311).
The claim that the law of inertia is just F = ma for the special case in which F = 0 is demonstrably false. The law of inertia is required to define the entity relative to which the second law holds, viz., an inertial frame (cf. Brown’s similar point in his 2005).
See Arnowitt et al. (2008) for the republication of the original 1962 paper.
Ruetsche (2011, p. 7) emphasis in the original. Saunders remarked similarly, “…we may read off the predicates of an interpretation from the mathematics of a theory, and, because theories are born interpreted, we have a rough and ready idea of the objects that they are predicates of.” Saunders (2003, pp. 290–291).
That close association has been challenged in the philosophy of physics literature (see the discussion of the debate in Lehmkuhl (2008) and Rey (2013) and the literature cited therein).
While the view I adopt is similar to Lehmkuhl’s (2008, p. 97) “Candidate 3: the metric—and all that it determines”, I believe considerations in Lehmkuhl’s excellent essay underwrite an inference to the best explanation argument for my assumed partial interpretation. That argument lurks behind the fact that almost all of the mathematical objects in the formalism of GTR thought to describe gravitation derive from the metric tensor. In this sense, their geometric and gravitational significance is parasitic on the geometric and gravitational significance of that sole fundamental tensor in the theory.
Rovelli’s (2004, pp. 33–34) remarks assume that the above partial interpretation is a part of Einstein’s metrical approach to GTR studies even if that’s not the case in quantum gravity studies. Norton (1989, p. 40) says that Einstein “calls the metric tensor the gravitational field.” See Einstein (1949, p. 685), Einstein (1952, p. 144), Einstein’s (2002, p. 33).
Carroll (2004, p. 50), Choquet-Bruhat (2009, p. 39), Geroch (2013, p. 65), Hartle (2003, p. 13) says “…the central idea of general relativity is that gravity arises from the curvature of spacetime—the four-dimensional union of space and time. Gravity is geometry.” (ibid.) emphasis in the original, Wald (1984, p. 9, cf. p. 68). Weinberg (1972, p. vii) clearly suggests that both (a) the geometrization of gravitation and (b) that the metric tensor represents the gravitational field are standard views (though he seems dissatisfied with at least (a)). Weinberg would go on to say that Einstein adhered to both (a) and (b). See also Rovelli (2004, p. 77). Cf. Lehmkuhl (2014) for a different perspective.
Class for Physics of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences (2011, p. 2).
I’m leaning slightly on Ruetsche (2011, p. 7). I do not whole-heartedly agree with her way of explicating a partial interpretation of GTR* for she injects into the partial interpretation axiomatic formalism (e.g., she explicitly includes Einstein’s field equations in GTR’s* partial interpretation). For me, the equations are the things being partially interpreted. They are not themselves the substantive content of the (partial) interpretation.
It is common in general relativity to call electromagnetic radiation a type of matter, though that is not the standard practice in particle physics (Rovelli 1997, p. 219. n. 10).
In 1916, Friedrich Kottler argued that Einstein interpreted the second term of the geodesic equation of motion in such a way that it described the gravitational field’s influence on massive bodies. Einstein would recognize this charge in Kottler’s work himself (see Einstein (1997, p. 238) I do not understand Einstein’s follow-up comment regarding meaninglessness. It does not cohere with what’s stated nor with Einstein’s general corpus.). He never corrected the causal nature of the interpretation attributed to him (see the interesting discussion of the relevant passages in Lehmkuhl (2014, p. 323)).
Einstein uses quasi-causal language when interpreting the geodesic equation of motion. In Einstein (2002, p. 339), for example, he said the geodesic equation of motion describes “the motion of a material particle under the action only of inertia and gravitation” (ibid. emphasis mine). A little later in the same work Einstein says of the geodesic equation of motion that it expresses “the influence of inertia and gravitation upon the material particle.” (ibid., p. 341) emphasis mine.
In dialog with Moritz Schlick about the nature of causation, Einstein (2006) interpreted gravitational phenomena causally.
Brown and and Lehmkuhl (2013, p. 3).
See Eddington (2014, pp. 125–127; cf. pp. 149–170), Einstein and Grommer (1927), Einstein, Infeld, and Hoffmann (1938), Einstein and Infeld (1940), Einstein and Infeld (1949), Fock (1959, pp. 215–218), Geroch and Jang (1975), Infeld and Schild (1949). The history of attempts to derive the law of motion for particles from the EFEs receives careful attention in Havas (1989); and Havas (1993).
Einstein admits in a letter to Ludwik Silberstein that “a really complete theory would exist only if the ‘matter’ could be represented in it by fields and without singularities.” As quoted in Havas (1993, p. 102) emphasis in the original.
“The fact that geodesic motion is a theorem and not a postulate has striking consequences that cannot be overemphasized. Earlier…I argued that it (and the need for corrections in the case of bodies with spin) casts doubt on the widespread view that space–time structure, in and of itself, can act directly on test bodies.” Brown (2005, p. 162).
Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler (1973, p. 476).
Geroch and Horowitz (1979, p. 212). In the perfect fluid case one clearly sees this in the presence of the Lorentz metric tensor in the energy–momentum tensor of the perfect fluid. Rovelli goes further: “…in all physical equations one now sees the direct influence of the gravitational field…any measurement of length, area or volume is, in reality, a measurement of features of the gravitational field”. Rovelli (1999, p. 7).
Misner, Thorne, and Wheeler (1973, p. 476).
See also Nerlich (1976, p. 264).
The coupling talk is particularly relevant for Lagrangian formulations of GTR, which Einstein utilized around 1918.
As quoted and translated by Pais (1982, p. 465). With respect to Einstein and the ultimate unified field theory, Pais (ibid.) goes on to remark, “He [Einstein] demanded that the theory shall be strictly causal, that it shall unify gravitation and electromagnetism, that the particles of physics shall emerge as special solutions of the general field equations…” emphasis mine
Also see his discussion (with Infeld) of the elevator thought experiment in Einstein and Infeld (1938, 226–235).
Robert Wald (personal correspondence, 12/18/2014). See also Geroch (1978, p. 180), (2013, p. 2, p. 65, p. 68), cf. Misner et al. (1973, pp. 476–477), Nerlich (1994), though not clearly committed to a causal interpretation of spacetime’s action says, “[b]ut GR surely makes spacetime something not easily distinguished from a real concrete entity with causal powers” (ibid., p. 183). And Carl Hoefer (2009, p. 702) says the causal interpretation is commonly accepted. Brown describes the position that spacetime in GTR acts as a view that is “widespread” (Brown 2005, p. 162). So far as I’m aware, neither Hoefer nor Brown endorse the causal interpretation I’m defending.
I’m ignoring the problem of specifying “choice” coordinates or a gauge.
More technically, for every timelike vector \( \xi^{\mu } \) associated with any point in the differentiable manifold representing spacetime the following relation holds: \( T_{\mu \nu } \xi^{\mu } \xi^{\nu } \ge 0 \). It is assumed that the energy–momentum tensor is appropriately related to the matter fields a hypothetical observer gives attention to. See the discussion in Malament (2009, pp. 6–7), Malament (2012a, p. 144) and Weatherall (2011).
As Geroch noted, “[e]verywhere, we see the metric, directly or indirectly, in the stress-energy…It appears that it is simply impossible to make any reasonable description of matter without the notions of space and time provided by the metric” Geroch (2013, p. 67). See also Hawking and Ellis (1973, p. 61), Malament (2012a, p. 160), Pooley (2013, p. 541. n. 38). The dependence holds even for Lagrangian formulations (see Lehmkuhl (2011, pp. 464–470)). Why is this true? The answer lies in the interpretation of GTR on offer (see Sect. 6.3).
“Gravity is one of the four fundamental interactions.” Hartle (2003, p. 3).
Birnbacher and Hommen (2013, p. 144) emphasis in the original. The authors are there concerned with a reductionist (the laws are non-causal) account of causation whose backbone is essentially the relation of nomological determination.
Glennan (2011, p. 811) points out that nomological determination is at home in a causal approach to laws of nature (mentioning the well-known causal account of David Armstrong inter alia).
DiSalle (1995, p. 327).
Chalmers (1996, p. 37) although Chalmers calls it natural supervenience.
Again see the characterization in Chalmers (1996, p. 37).
The Merlin case may strike one as too bizarre. Give attention then to any scenario in which something begins to exist on account of a preexisting cause. I, an agent, made a decision to write this paper. Even if agent causation reduces to event causation, and even if mental causation reduces to something non-causal, no problems arise. A plethora of events causally produced a decision, a mental event that was not around before. The decision depends for its existence and nature upon the preceding physical (and perhaps mental) events. If causal reductionism is right, the relevant instance of mental causation reduces to something non-causal, though (importantly) it is not eliminated. Causal reductionism is not causal eliminativism. We have therefore an instance of mental causation, but also an instance of grounding irrespective of whether or not causal reductionism holds.
Hawking and Ellis (1973, p. 183) emphasis mine.
Geroch (2013, p. 123) emphasis mine. Geroch uses ‘I-(p)’ to represent p’s past domain of influence. I am widening Geroch’s notion of a domain of influence a bit since even he admits that the term can be misleading, since I-(p) (having to do with the narrower conception of a past domain of influence) “does not include its boundary, whereas points on the boundary can, in general, also influence p” (ibid., p. 123). I am deliberately intending to include the boundary. In so doing, I follow Bhattacharyya’s et al. (2016, p. 17) identification of domains of influence with causal pasts and futures. Cf. Manchak (2013, p. 590), Ellis and Stoeger (2009).
In this section, I am not arguing that causal structure is causally efficacious. I am not arguing that the specific geometric features standing behind causal structure are themselves causally efficacious. The argument in this section is that there’s a type of structure to spacetime that cosmology needs that is causal in that it is explicitly defined in causal terms. That causal taint cannot be dispensed with because that causal structure cannot be identified with any non-causal structure such as light or null cone structure. So the stuff about light/null cones and causal structure is independent of the stuff about the causal efficaciousness of the gravitational field/metric field or spacetime geometry previously discussed in this paper.
Gravitational lensing involving matter or associated caustics can produce a collapse or folding in of the light cone induced by a vertex point p in the manifold (Ellis et al. 1998, pp. 2346–2347); Schutz says “…even a small amount of matter in spacetime will distort light-cones enough to make them fold over on themselves.” (p. 336)). That folding can entail that part of the (past or future) cone bends inside of the causal past or future of p (Perlick 2004; Tavakol and Ellis 1999, p. 41 who include further references on this point). The past/future light cone and the causal past/future of p cannot therefore be identical. Thanks to George Ellis for help with references.
The mistake of identifying causal structure in relativity with light cone structure is often committed by philosophers (see e.g., Frisch (2014, pp. 16–17), Field (2003, p. 436) comes close to suggesting such identification). Causal or influence structure is standardly regarded as more fundamental than light cone structure in GTR (see Geroch 2013, p. 125).
Hardy (2007, pp. 3084–3085).
Rickles (2008, p. 347. n. 124) emphasis mine. The quote’s immediate context is about Robb’s formulation of STR, but it’s clear from context that Rickles is also intending to characterize causal set approaches to quantum gravity.
Newton (1999, p. 405) italics removed.
Friedman et al. (1990, p. 1915).
Cf. Stephen Hawking (1992).
Thus, one can endorse the conclusions and resolutions of time travel paradoxes in Earman et al. (2009, pp. 93–100) and yet hold on to the supposition that the introduction of principles like SCP is not unscientific.
This is what Ned Hall (2004, p. 266) calls a “Mackie-style regularity account”.
The same argument will run with minimal fundamentalist causation in mind.
As quoted by Wheeler (1998, p. 235).
The gravitational field never vanishes even under coordinate transformations, and even in the absence of matter. Moreover, gravitational radiation can propagate in a vacuum.
Lehmkuhl does not deny that there is interaction between metric field and matter in GTR. He said that “…the matter fields and the metric field gμνare interacting in GR…” Lehmkuhl (2011, p. 469) emphasis in the original.
Einstein said,
“That something real has to be conceived as the cause for the preference of an inertial system over a non-inertial system is a fact that physicists have only come to understand in recent years….Also, following the special theory of relativity, the ether [features of Minkowski spacetime geometry] was absolute, because its influence on inertia and light propagation was thought to be independent of physical influences of any kind…” As quoted and translated by Brown and Pooley (2006, p. 68). Einstein said this in 1924.
Brown and Pooley would go on to remark that “[i]t was Einstein’s view, then, both that the inertial property of matter can be explained, and that this explanation is to be given in terms of the action of a real entity on the particles”. Brown and Pooley (2006, p. 68).
Continuing to use the theory in Schaffer’s (2009).
Lehmkuhl (2011, p. 467) emphasis in the original.
It is important to point out that Lehmkuhl believes that the causal interaction of fields is a sufficient condition for direct coupling (see Lehmkuhl 2011, p. 469). He too sees room for a relationship between interaction and coupling.
I am assuming that substantivalism is the view that spacetime exists as a substance (quoting Sklar) “independently of the existence of any ordinary material objects, where the latter phrase is taken to include even such extraordinary material objects as rays of light, physical fields…etc.” Sklar (1976, p. 161)
On the basis of parsimony motivations, Brown (2005, pp. 24–25) argues against the view that spacetime structure plays an explanatory role in accounting for the motions of bodies. Cf. the discussion in DiSalle (1994, p. 276) and DiSalle (1995, p. 327).
See the comments in Arntzenius (2012, p. 17 “[a]ccording to…[GTR] spacetime, again, is a single four-dimensional entity.” (ibid.)), and Nerlich (2003, p. 281). In general, a realist approach to our most successful theories of physics suggests spacetime substantivalism (see the comments in Pooley 2013, p. 539; Sklar 1976, p. 214; cf. Weinstein 2001 who argues that relationalism is tough to defend in the context of quantum physics).
I do have reservations about such an interpretation.
Although later in Rovelli (2004), he seems to think of his choice position as relationalist. He said, “Thus, both GR and QM are characterized by a form of relationalism.” (ibid., p. 220).
Rovelli (1997, p. 193). Weyl compared the gravitational field’s action to the productive (causal) behavior of the electric field. He said,
…just as the electric field, for its part, depends on the charges and is instrumental in producing a mechanical interaction between the charges, so we must assume here that the metrical field…is related to the material content filling the world. Weyl (1952, p. 220) emphasis in the original
In his ontology of physics, Weyl made room for a guidance field that appears to be causal (see Coleman and Korté (2001, p. 198) and the sources cited therein).
The idea that the geometric interpretation precludes a causal understanding of gravitational effects is expressed in many places, but see Livanios (2008, p. 390) who writes, “…[i]t is clear that if we adopt a 4-dimensional ontological framework,…and geometrise away the gravitational field, spacetime does not causally affect matter.”
I find it interesting that in one of the most exhaustive and most recent discussions of non-causal explanations in science and mathematics (explanations from constraint in Lange 2017), the section on geometric non-causal explanation (see specifically ibid., pp. 126–128) does not take up these matters having to do with geodesic motion and the gravitational field. Even if it did, Lange’s treatise seems most chiefly concerned with explanation. I’m interested in the ontology, what reality needs to be like to back explanations. I happen to think that obtaining causal relations can back non-causal (as well as causal) explanations. In fact, I think certain mathematical truths hold because (this is a because without cause that is indicative of a distinctive non-causal metaphysical explanation such as truth-making or grounding) certain causal relations obtain. Is this not suggested by causally interpreting mathematical formalism?
References
Armstrong, D. M. (1997). A world of states of affairs. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Arnowitt, R., Deser, S., & Misner, C. W. (2008). Republication of: The dynamics of general relativity. General Relativity and Gravitation,40, 1997–2027.
Arntzenius, F. (2012). Space, time, and stuff. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Aronson, J. L. (1971). On the grammar of ‘Cause’. Synthese,22, 414–430.
Balashov, Y., & Janssen, M. (2003). Review: Presentism and Relativity. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,54, 327–346.
Beebee, H., Hitchcock, C., & Menzies, P. (2009). Introduction. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 1–18). New York: Oxford University Press.
Belot, G. (2011). Geometric possibility. New York: Oxford University Press.
Belot, G. (1996). Why general relativity does need an interpretation. Philosophy of Science. 63, Supplement: In Proceedings of the 1996 Biennial Meetings of the Philosophy of Science Association. Part I: Contributed Papers: S80–S88.
Ben-Menahem, Y. (1993). Struggling with causality: Einstein’s case. Science in Context,6, 291–310.
Bennett, K. (2017). Making things up. New York: Oxford University Press.
Bhattacharyya, J., Colombo, M., & Sotiriou, T. P. (2016). Causality and black holes in spacetimes with a preferred foliation. Classical and Quantum Gravity,33, 235003.
Birnbacher, D., & Hommen, D. (2013). Omissions as causes—Genuine, quasi, or not at all? In K. Kahmen & M. Stepanians (Eds.), Critical essays on “Causation and Responsibility” (pp. 133–156). Urbana: Walter De Gruyter and Co.
Brown, H. R. (2005). Physical relativity: Space-time structure from a dynamical perspective. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Brown, H. R. (2009). The behaviour of rods and clocks in general relativity, and the meaning of the metric field. arXiv:0911.4440v1 [gr-qc] 23 Nov 2009.
Brown, H. R. and Lehmkuhl, D. (2013). Einstein, the reality of space, and the action-reaction principle. arXiv:1306.4902v1 [physics.hist-ph] 20 Jun 2013.
Brown, H. R., & Pooley, O. (2006). Minkowsi space-time: A glorious non-entity. In D. Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime (pp. 67–89). Amsterdam: Elsevier.
Carnap, R. (1967). The logical structure of the world: Pseudoproblems in philosophy. Trans. by Rolf A. George. George: University of California Press.
Carroll, S. M. (2004). Spacetime and geometry: An introduction to general relativity. San Francisco, CA: Addison Wesley.
Carroll, J. W. (2009). Anti-reductionism. In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock, & Peter Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 279–298). New York: Oxford University Press.
Cartwright, N. (1993). In defence of ‘This Worldly’ causality: Comments on van Fraassen’s laws and symmetry. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research,53, 423–429.
Chalmers, D. J. (1996). The conscious mind. In search of a fundamental theory. New York: Oxford University Press.
Choquet-Bruhat, Y. (2009). General relativity and the Einstein equations. New York: Oxford University Press.
Clarke, R. (2014). Omissions: Agency, metaphysics, and responsibility. New York: Oxford University Press.
Class for Physics of the Royal Swedish Academy of Sciences. 2011. Scientific background on the nobel prize in physics 2011: The accelerating universe. http://www.nobelprize.org/nobel_prizes/physics/laureates/2011/advanced-physicsprize2011.pdf.
Coleman, R. A., & Korté, H. (2001). Hermann Weyl: Mathematician, physicist, philosopher. In E. Scholz (Ed.), Hermann Weyl’s Raum-Zeit-Materie and a general introduction to his scientific work (pp. 161–386). Basel AG: Springer.
Craig, W. L. (2001). Time and the metaphysics of relativity. Philosophical Studies Series (Vol. 84). Dordrecht: Kluwer.
Craig, W. L. (2008). The metaphysics of special relativity: Three views. In W. L. Craig & Q. Smith (Eds.), Einstein, relativity and absolute simultaneity (pp. 11–49). New York: Routledge Publishers.
Curiel, E. (2009). General relativity needs no interpretation. Philosophy of Science,76, 44–72.
Curiel, E. (2014). A primer on energy conditions. arXiv:1405.0403v1 [physics.hist-ph] 30 Apr 2014.
DiSalle, R. (1994). On dynamics, indiscernibility, and spacetime ontology. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,45, 265–287.
DiSalle, R. (1995). Spacetime theory as physical geometry. Erkenntnis,42, 317–337.
Dodelson, S. (2017). Gravitational lensing. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Dowe, P. (2000). Physical causation (Cambridge studies in probability, induction, and decision theory). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Dowe, P. (2004). Causes are physically connected to their effects: Why preventers and omissions are not causes. In H. Christopher (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science. (Contemporary Debates in Philosophy) (pp. 189–196). Malden: Blackwell Publishers.
Earman, J. (1995). Bangs, crunches, whimpers, and shrieks: Singularities and acausalities in relativistic spacetimes. New York: Oxford University Press.
Earman, J., Smeenk, C., & Wüthrich, C. (2009). Do the laws of physics forbid the operation of time machines? Synthese,169, 91–124.
Eddington, A. S. (2014). The mathematical theory of relativity. Originally published Cambridge: Cambridge University Press, 1923. Reprinted Lexington, KY: Bibliolife, 2014.
Ehlers, J. (1987). Folklore in relativity and what is really known, in M.A.H. MacCallum (ed.), General relativity and gravitation: Proceedings of the 11th international conference on general relativity and gravitation. New York, NY: Cambridge University Press, pp. 61–71.
Einstein, A. (1929). Ansprache von Prof. Einstein an Prof. Planck. Sitzungsberichte Wissenschaftlicher Körperschaften. Forschungen und Fortschritte. Nachrichtenblatt Der Deutschen Wissenschaft und Technik. Fünfter Jahnrgang. pp. 248–249.
Einstein, A. (1949). Remarks concerning the essays brought together in this co-operative volume, In P. A. Schilpp (ed.), Albert Einstein: Philosopher-Scientist. 665-688. Evanston, IL: The Library of Living Philosophers, Inc.
Einstein, A. (1950). The meaning of relativity. Third Edition, including the generalized theory of gravitation. Trans. by Edwin P. Adams, Appendix I trans. by Ernst G. Straus. Appendix II translated by Sonja Bargmann. Princeton: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (1952). The foundation of the general theory of relativity, In H.A. Lorentz, A. Einstein, H. Minkowski, and H. Weyl with notes by A. Sommerfeld and trans. by W. Perrett and G.B. Jeffery, The principle of relativity: A collection of original memoirs on the special and general theory of relativity. New York, NY: Dover Publications, Inc., pp. 111–164.
Einstein, A. (1954). Ideas and opinions. New York, NY: Crown Publishers, Inc. Based on Mein Weltbild edited by Carl Seelig and other sources. New translations and revisions by Sonja Bargmann. New York: Bonanza Books.
Einstein, A. (1997). The collected papers of Albert Einstein: Volume 6 (English): The Berlin Years: Writings, 1914–1917. (English Translation Supplement) Trans. by Alfred Engel. Engelbert Schucking, Consultant. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (2002). The collected papers of Albert Einstein: Volume 7, The Berlin Years: Writings, 1918–1921 English Translation of Selected Texts. English trans. by Alfred Engel. Engelbert Schucking, Consultant. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Einstein, A. (2006). Letter to Moritz Schlick [Berlin] June 1920”, Document 47 In The collected papers of Albert Einstein: Volume 10 The Berlin Years: Correspondence, May–December 1920 and Supplementary Correspondence, 1909–1920. Edited by D. Kormos Buchwald, T. Sauer, Z. Rosenkrantz, J. Illy, and V. I. Holmes. Trans. by Ann Hentschel. Klaus Hentschel, Consultant. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press, pp. 186–187.
Einstein, A. (2013). The meaning of relativity: Four lectures delivered at Princeton University, May, 1921. Edited by J. Gahan, translated by E. P. Adams. Princeton: Princeton University Press Reprinted by Desmondous Publications, 2013.
Einstein, A. and Grommer, J. (1927). Allgemeine Relativitätstheorie und Bewegungsgesetz. Sitzungsberichte der Preussischen Akademie der Wissenschaften, Physikalisch-Mathematische Klasse. 2–13
Einstein, A., & Infeld, L. (1938). The evolution of physics: The growth of ideas from early concepts to relativity and quanta. New York: Simon and Schuster.a.
Einstein, A., & Infeld, L. (1940). The gravitational equations and the problem of motion II. Annals of Mathematics. Second Series.,41, 455–464.
Einstein, A., & Infeld, L. (1949). On the motion of particles in general relativity theory. Canadian Journal of Mathematics,1, 209–241.
Einstein, A., Infeld, L., & Hoffmann, B. (1938). The gravitational equations and the problem of motion. Annals of Mathematics Second Series,39, 65–100.
Ellis, G. F. R., Bassett, B. A. C. C., & Dunsby, P. K. S. (1998). Lensing and caustic effects on cosmological distances. Classical and Quantum Gravity,15, 2345–2361.
Ellis, G. F. R., & Stoeger, W. R. (2009). The evolution of our local cosmic domain: Effective causal limits. Monthly Notices of the Royal Astronomical Society,398, 1527–1536.
Fair, D. (1979). Causation and the flow of energy. Erkenntnis,14, 219–250.
Field, H. (2003). Causation in a physical world. In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 435–460). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Fock, V. (1959). The Theory of Space. Time and Gravitation. translated by N. Kemmer. London: Pergamon Press LTD.
Foster, J., & Nightingale, J. D. (2005). A short course in general relativity (3rd ed.). New York: Springer.
Friedman, J., Morris, M. S., Novikov, I. D., Encheverria, F., Klinkhammer, G., Thorne, K. S., et al. (1990). Cauchy problem in spacetimes with closed timelike curves. Physical Review D.,42, 1915–1930.
Frisch, M. (2005). Inconsistency, asymmetry, and non-locality: A philosophical investigation of classical electrodynamics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Frisch, M. (2014). Causal reasoning in Physics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Geroch, R. (1978). General Relativity: From A to B. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Geroch, R. (2013). General relativity: 1972 lecture notes. Montreal and Quebec, Canada: Minkowski Institute Press.
Geroch, R., & Horowitz, G. T. (1979). Global structure of spacetimes. In S. W. Hawking & W. Israel (Eds.), General relativity: An Einstein centenary survey (pp. 212–293). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Geroch, R., & Jang, P. S. (1975). Motion of a body in general relativity. Journal of Mathematical Physics,16, 65–67.
Giere, R. N. (1988). Explaining science: A cognitive approach. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Gillett, C. (2003). The metaphysics of realization, multiple realizability, and the special sciences. The Journal of Philosophy.,100, 591–603.
Glennan, S. (2011). Singular and general causal relations: A mechanist perspective. In P. McKay Illari & J. Williamson (Eds.), Causality in the Sciences (pp. 789–817). New York: Oxford University Press.
Hall, N. (2004). The intrinsic character of causation. In Dean W. Zimmerman (Ed.), Oxford studies in metaphysics (pp. 255–300). New York: Oxford University Press.
Hall, N. (2011). Causation and the sciences. In Steven French & Juha Saatsi (Eds.), The continuum companion to the philosophy of science (pp. 96–119). London: Continuum International Publishing Group.
Hall, N. (2015). Humean reductionism about laws of nature. In B. Loewer & J. Schaffer (Eds.), A companion to David Lewis (Blackwell Companions to David Lewis) (pp. 262–277). Wiley Blackwell: Malden, MA.
Hardy, L. (2007). Towards quantum gravity: A framework for probabilistic theories with non-fixed causal structure. Journal of Physics A: Mathematical and Theoretical,40, 3081–3099.
Hartle, J. B. (2003). Gravity: An introduction to Einstein’s general relativity. San Francisco, CA: Addison Wesley.
Havas, P. (1989). The early history of the ‘Problem of Motion’ in general relativity. In D. Howard and J. Stachel (eds.), Einstein and the history of general relativity. Based on the proceedings of the 1986 Osgood Hill Conference, North Andover, Massachusetts 8–11 May 1986. Boston, MA: Birkhäuser, 234–276.
Havas, P. (1993). The general-relativistic two-body problem and the Einstein–Silberstein controversy. In J. Earman, M. Janssen, & J. D. Norton (Eds.), The attraction of gravitation: New studies in the history of general relativity (Einstein Studies Volume 5) (pp. 88–125). Boston, MA: Birkhäuser.
Hawking, S. W. (1992). Chronology protection conjecture. Physical Review D.,46, 603–611.
Hawking, S. W. (1996). Classical theory. In S. Hawking & R. Penrose (Eds.), The nature of space and time (pp. 3–26). New Jersey, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Hawking, S. W., & Ellis, G. F. R. (1973). The large scale structure of space-time. (Cambridge Monographs on Mathematical Physics). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Heathcote, A. (1989). A theory of causality: Causality = interaction (as defined by a suitable quantum field theory). Erkenntnis,31, 77–108.
Hellman, G., & Thompson, F. W. (1977). Physicalist materialism. Noûs,11, 309–345.
Hempel, C. G. (1965). Aspects of scientific explanation: And other essays in the philosophy of science. New York: The Free Press.
Hitchcock, C. (2004). Causal processes and interactions: What are they and what are they good for? Philosophy of Science,71(5), 932–941.
Hitchcock, C. (2007). What Russell Got Right. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s republic revisited (pp. 45–65). Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Hoefer, C. (2009). Causation in spacetime theories. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 687–706). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Infeld, L. (1954). On the motion of bodies in general relativity theory. Acta Physica Polinica.,13, 187–204.
Infeld, L. (1957). Equations of motion in general relativity theory and the action principle. Reviews of Modern Physics,29, 398–411.
Infeld, L., & Schild, A. (1949). On the motion of test particles in general relativity. Reviews of Modern Physics,21, 408–413.
Jammer, Max. (1957). Concepts of force: A study in the foundations of dynamics. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Janssen, M. (2012). The twins and the bucket: How Einstein made gravity rather than motion relative in general relativity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics.,43, 159–175.
Kutach, D. (2013). Causation and its basis in fundamental physics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lambourne, R. J. A. (2010). Relativity, gravitation and cosmology. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Lange, M. (2017). Because without cause: Non-causal explanations in science and mathematics. New York: Oxford University Press.
Lee, J. M. (2009). Manifolds and differential geometry. Rhode Island: American Mathematical Society.
Lehmkuhl, D. (2008). Is spacetime a gravitational field? In Dennis Dieks (Ed.), The ontology of spacetime II (philosophy and foundations of physics) (Vol. 4, pp. 83–110). Elsevier B.V.: The Netherlands.
Lehmkuhl, D. (2011). Mass-Energy-Momentum: Only There Because of Spacetime? The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,62, 453–488.
Lehmkuhl, D. (2014). Why Einstein did not believe that general relativity geometrizes gravity. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics,46, 316–326.
Lewis, D. (1973). Counterfactuals. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Lewis, D. (1983). New work for a theory of universals. Australasian Journal of Philosophy,61, 343–377.
Lewis, D. (1986a). Causation. In D. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers volume II (pp. 159–172). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Lewis, D. (1986b). On the plurality of worlds. Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Lewis, D. (1986c). Postscripts to ‘Causation’. In D. K. Lewis (Ed.), Philosophical papers (Vol. II, pp. 172–213). New York: Oxford University Press.
Lewis, D. (1994). Humean supervenience debugged. Mind,103, 473–490.
Lewis, D. (2004). Causation as influence. In J. Collins, N. Hall, & L. A. Paul (Eds.), Causation and counterfactuals (pp. 75–106). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Livanios, V. (2008). Bird and the dispositional essentialist account of spatiotemporal relations. Journal for General Philosophy of Science,39, 383–394.
Loewer, B. (2012). Two accounts of laws and time. Philosophical Studies,160, 115–137.
Lowe, E. J. (2016). There are (probably) no relations. In Anna Marmodoro & David Yates (Eds.), The metaphysics of relations (pp. 100–112). Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Malament, D.B. (2009). On the Status of the ‘Geodesic Law’ in General Relativity Version 2.0. http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/4908/1/GeodesicLaw.pdf downloaded 12/29/2015.
Malament, D. B. (2012a). Topics in the foundations of general relativity and newtonian gravitation theory. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Malament, D. B. (2012b). A Remark about the ‘Geodesic Principle’ in General Relativity. In Mélanie Frapier, Derek H. Brown, & Robert DiSalle (Eds.), Analysis and interpretation in the exact sciences: Essays in honour of William Demopoulos (pp. 245–252). Dordrecht: Springer.
Manchak, J. B. (2013). Global spacetime structure. In Robert Batterman (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of physics (pp. 587–606). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Maudlin, T. (2007). The metaphysics within physics. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Menzies, P., & Price, H. (1993). Causation as a secondary quality. The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,44, 187–203.
Misner, C. W., Thorne, K. S., & Wheeler, J. A. (1973). Gravitation. San Francisco, CA: W.H. Freeman and Company.
Morris, M. S., Thorne, K. S., & Yurtsever, U. (1988). Wormholes, time machines, and the weak energy condition. Physical Review Letters,61, 1446–1449.
Mumford, S., & Anjum, R. L. (2011). Getting causes from powers. New York: Oxford University Press.
Nerlich, G. (1976). The shape of space. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Nerlich, G. (1994). What spacetime explains: Metaphysical essays on space and time. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Nerlich, G. (2003). Space-time substantivalism. In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 281–314). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Newton, I. (1999). The Principia: Mathematical Principles of Natural Philosophy. Translated by I. Bernard Cohen and Anne Whitman assisted by Julia Budenz. Preceded by A Guide to Newton’s Principia by I. Bernard Cohen. Berkeley and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Norton, J. (1989). What was Einstein’s Principle of Equivalence? In D. Howard and J. Stachel (eds.), Einstein and the History of General Relativity: Einstein Studies Volume 1. Based on the Proceedings of the 1986 Osgood Hill Conference, North Andover, Massachusetts 8–11 May 1986. Boston, MA: Birkhäuser, 5–47.
Norton, J. (2007a). Causation as Folk Science. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation, physics, and the constitution of reality: Russell’s Republic Revisited (pp. 11–44). New York: Oxford University Press.
Norton, J. (2007b). Do the causal principles of modern physics contradict causal anti-fundamentalism? In P. Machamer & G. Wolters (Eds.), Thinking about causes: From Greek Philosophy to modern physics (pp. 222–234). Pittsburg, PN: University of Pittsburgh Press.
Norton, J. (2015). What can we learn about the ontology of space and time from the theory of relativity? In Lawrence Sklar (Ed.), Physical theory: Method and interpretation (pp. 185–228). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Pais, A. (1982). Subtle is the Lord: The science and the life of Albert Einstein. New York: Oxford University Press.
Pais, A. (1991). Niels Bohr’s times, in physics, philosophy and polity. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
Paul, L. A. (2009). Counterfactual theories. In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock, & Peter Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 158–184). New York: Oxford University Press.
Paul, L. A., & Hall, N. (2013). Causation: A user’s guide. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Pearl, J. (2009). Causality: Models, reasoning, and inference (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Penrose, R. (2005). The road to reality: A complete guide to the laws of the universe. New York: Vintage Books.
Perlick, V. (2004). Gravitational lensing from a spacetime perspective. Living Reviews in Relativity,7(1), 9.
Pooley, O. (2013). Substantivalist and relationalist approaches to spacetime. In B. Robert (Ed.), The Oxford handbook of philosophy of physics (pp. 522–586). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Post, J. F. (1987). The faces of existence: An essay in nonreductive metaphysics. Ithaca, NY: Cornell University Press.
Prugovečki, E. (1995). Principles of quantum general relativity. Singapore: World Scientific.
Psillos, S. (2009). Regularity theories. In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock, & Peter Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 131–157). New York: Oxford University Press.
Quine, W. V. O. (1951). Ontology and ideology. Philosophical Studies,2, 11–15.
Rey, D. (2013). Similarity assessments, spacetime, and the gravitational field: What does the metric tensor represent in general relativity? http://philsci-archive.pitt.edu/id/eprint/9615 Foundations of Physics 2013: The 17th UK and European Meeting on the Foundations of Physics (Munich; 29-31 July 2013).
Rickles, D. (2008). Quantum Gravity: A Primer for Philosophers. In Dean Rickles (Ed.), The Ashgate companion to contemporary philosophy of physics (pp. 262–383). Aldershot and Burlington: Ashgate Publishing Limited and Ashgate Publishing Company.
Rindler, W. (2006). Relativity: Special, general and cosmological (2nd ed.). New York: Oxford University Press.
Romero, C., Fonseca-Neto, J. B., & Pucheu, M. L. (2011). General relativity and weyl frames. International Journal of Modern Physics: Conference Series.,3, 27–35.
Rovelli, C. (1997). Halfway through the Woods: Contemporary research on space and time. In John Earman & John D. Norton (Eds.), The cosmos of science: Essays of exploration (pp. 180–223). Pittsburg, PN: University of Pittsburg Press.
Rovelli, C. (1999). Quantum spacetime: What do we know? arXiv:gr-qc/9903045v1. 12 Mar 1999.
Rovelli, C. (2004). Quantum gravity (Cambridge monographs on mathematical physics). New York, NY: Cambridge University Press.
Rueger, A. (1998). Local theories of causation and the a posteriori identification of the causal relation. Erkenntnis,48, 25–38.
Ruetsche, L. (2011). Interpreting quantum theories: The art of the possible. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Russell, B. (1912–1913). On the notion of cause, in Proceedings of the Aristotelian Society 13, pp. 1–26.
Salmon, W. C. (1984). Scientific explanation and the causal structure of the world. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Saunders, S. (2003). Physics and Leibniz’s principles. In B. Katherine & C. Elena (Eds.), Symmetries in physics: Philosophical reflections (pp. 289–307). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.
Schaffer, J. (2000). Trumping preemption. The Journal of Philosophy.,97, 165–181.
Schaffer, J. (2004). Causes need not be physically connected to their effects: The case for negative causation. In Christopher Hitchcock (Ed.), Contemporary debates in philosophy of science (Contemporary Debates in Philosophy) (pp. 197–216). Malden, MA: Blackwell Publishing.
Schaffer, J. (2007). Review: Dowe and Noordhof. Cause and Chance, The British Journal for the Philosophy of Science,58, 869–874.
Schaffer, J. (2008). Causation and laws of nature: Reductionism. In Theodore Sider, John Hawthorne, & Dean W. Zimmerman (Eds.), Contemporary Debates in Metaphysics (Contemporary Debates in Philosophy) Malden (pp. 82–107). MA: Blackwell Publishers.
Schaffer, J. (2009). On what grounds what. In David J. Chalmers, David Manley, & Ryan Wasserman (Eds.), Metametaphysics: New essays on the foundations of ontology (pp. 347–383). New York: Oxford University Press.
Schaffer, J. (2010). The internal relatedness of all things. Mind,119, 341–376.
Schaffer, J. (2016). The metaphysics of causation”, In Edward N. Zalta (ed.), The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Fall 2016 Edition). https://plato.stanford.edu/archives/fall2016/entries/causation-metaphysics/.
Schutz, B. (2003). Gravity from the ground up: An introductory guide to gravity and general relativity. New York: Cambridge University Press.
Sklar, L. (1976). Space, time, and spacetime. Berkely and Los Angeles, CA: University of California Press.
Spirtes, P., Glymour, C., & Scheines, R. (2000). Causation, prediction and search (2nd ed.). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
Strevens, M. (2008). Depth: An account of scientific explanation. Cambridge, MA: Harvard University Press.
Suppe, F. (1989). The semantic conception of theories and scientific realism. Urbana and Chicago, IL: University of Illinois Press.
Tamir, M. (2012). Proving the principle: Taking geodesic dynamics too seriously in Einstein’s theory. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics,43, 137–154.
Tavakol, R., & Ellis, G. (1999). Holography and comsology. Physics Letters B,469, 37–45.
Tavakol, R., & Zalaletdinov, R. (1998). On the domain of applicability of general relativity. Foundations of Physics,28, 307–331.
Thorne, K. S. (1994). Black holes and time warps: Einstein’s outrageous legacy. New York: W.W. Norton & Company.
Tooley, M. (1987). Causation: A realist approach. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Tooley, M. (2003). Causation and Supervenience. In Michael J. Loux & Dean W. Zimmerman (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of metaphysics (pp. 386–434). New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Torretti, R. (1983). Relativity and geometry. New York: Pergamon Press.
van Fraassen, B. C. (1970). On the extension of Beth’s semantics of physical theories. Philosophy of Science,37, 325–339.
van Fraassen, B. C. (1989). Laws and symmetry. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
van Fraassen, B. C. (1991). Quantum mechanics: An empiricist view. Oxford: Clarendon Press.
van Fraassen, B. C. (2008). Scientific representation: Paradoxes of perspective. New York: Oxford University Press.
Wald, R. M. (1984). General relativity. Chicago, IL: University of Chicago Press.
Wall, A. C. (2013). A discrete, unitary, causal theory of quantum gravity. Classical and Quantum Gravity,30, 115002.
Weatherall, J.O. (2011). A brief remark on energy conditions and the Geroch–Jang theorem. arXiv:1106.2336v1 [physics.hist-ph] 12 Jun 2011.
Weinberg, S. (1972). Gravitation and cosmology: Principles and applications of the general theory of relativity. New York: John Wiley & Sons Inc.
Weinberg, S. (2008). Cosmology. New York, NY: Oxford University Press.
Weinert, F. (2005). The scientist as philosopher: Philosophical consequences of great scientific discoveries. Berlin: Springer-Verlag.
Weinstein, S. (2001). Absolute quantum mechanics. The British Journal for Philosophy of Science,52, 67–73.
Westfall, R. S. (1971). Force in Newton’s Physics: The science of dynamics in the Seventeenth Century. New York, NY: American Elsevier.
Weyl, H. (1952). Space—time—matter. Fourth Edition. Translated by Henry L. Brose (4th ed.). Mineola NY: Dover Publications.
Wheeler, J. A. (1998). With Kenneth Ford. Geons, Black holes, and Quantum Foam: A Life in Physics. New York, NY: W.W. Norton and Company.
Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen: A theory of causal explanation. New York: Oxford University Press.
Woodward, J. (2009). Agency and interventionist theories. In Helen Beebee, Christopher Hitchcock, & Peter Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook of causation (pp. 234–262). New York: Oxford University Press.
Zee, A. (2013). Einstein gravity in a nutshell. Princeton, NJ: Princeton University Press.
Acknowledgements
I presented earlier versions of this paper at the 2014 Eastern American Philosophical Association conference, Mississippi State University, the University of Illinois at Urbana-Champaign, and Yale University. I thank my audiences at those institutions for their comments. I also thank two anonymous referees with Erkenntnis for their helpful comments and criticisms. The paper has benefited from correspondence with and/or comments from and/or discussions with David Albert, Tom Banks, David Black, Eddy Keming Chen, Shamik Dasgupta, George Ellis, Ned Hall, Michael Townsen Hicks, Barry Loewer, John Norton, Don Page, Laurie Paul, Joshua Rasmussen, Carlo Rovelli, Daniel Rubio, Jonathan Schaffer, Peter van Elswyk, Robert Wald, Aron Wall, and Dean Zimmerman. I thank all of these individuals for their help. Any mistakes that remain are mine.
Author information
Authors and Affiliations
Corresponding author
Rights and permissions
About this article
Cite this article
Weaver, C.G. On the Argument from Physics and General Relativity. Erkenn 85, 333–373 (2020). https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0030-8
Received:
Accepted:
Published:
Issue Date:
DOI: https://doi.org/10.1007/s10670-018-0030-8