Skip to main content

Top-Down Causation Without Levels

  • Chapter
  • First Online:
Top-Down Causation and Emergence

Part of the book series: Synthese Library ((SYLI,volume 439))

  • 884 Accesses

  • 3 Citations

Abstract

The paper addresses a question concerning George Ellis’s theory of top-down causation by considering a challenge to the “level-picture of nature” which he employs as a foundational element in his theory. According to the level-picture, nature is ordered by distinct and finitely many levels, each characterised by its own types of entities, relations, laws and principles of behavior, and causal relations to their respective neighbouring top- and bottom-level. The branching hierarchy that results from this picture enables Ellis to build his model of modular hierarchical structure for complexity, his account of same-level, bottom-up and top-down causation, of emergence, equivalence-classes and multiple realisability. The three main arguments for the level-picture in Ellis’s works are reconstructed and shown to face serious problems. Finally, the paper presents a possible solution to this challenge by introducing a reformulation of certain fundamental points of Ellis’s theory that does without the level-picture of nature. This allows us to preserve all of his central claims about the model of complexity, the three types of causation, emergence, equivalence-classes and multiple realisability. Any problems pertaining to the level-picture can be remedied in the context of Ellis’s theory of top-down causation.

This is a preview of subscription content, log in via an institution to check access.

Access this chapter

Subscribe and save

Springer+
from $39.99 /Month
  • Starting from 10 chapters or articles per month
  • Access and download chapters and articles from more than 300k books and 2,500 journals
  • Cancel anytime
View plans

Buy Now

Chapter
USD 29.95
Price excludes VAT (USA)
eBook
USD 129.00
Price excludes VAT (USA)
Softcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)
Hardcover Book
USD 169.99
Price excludes VAT (USA)

Tax calculation will be finalised at checkout

Purchases are for personal use only

Institutional subscriptions

Similar content being viewed by others

Notes

  1. 1.

    This definition applies to many different theories of causation; it is neither limited to Ellis nor meant to imply that his proposal originated the level-picture. The latter can be traced back at least to Anderson (1972), who introduced this kind of formulation into the debates about emergence and causation. Thus defined, the level-picture is a broad concept with a long history in thinking about nature. Yet in every different theory of emergence and causation its defining features change considerably. Any critique has to focus on the particular analysis at issue. George Ellis’s theory is a perfect case in point, not only due to its substantial weight in the debate on causality in the sciences and philosophy, but on account of its clarity regarding the role of levels. For other literature on the level-picture in the aforementioned debates see (Kim 1992, 1999, Emmeche et al. 1997, 2000, Hulswit 2005, Paolini Paoletti and Orilia 2017).

  2. 2.

    There is an extensive ongoing discussion in the philosophy of causation on the issue of pluralism and monism, see (Longworth 2006; Williamson 2006; Cartwright 2006, 2007; Psillos 2010; de Vreese 2010; Strevens 2013).

  3. 3.

    “Genuine complexity can only emerge from interlevel causation (both bottom-up and top-down) in modular hierarchical structures. […] The structure is emergent from lower level entities, but is much more than the parts. It is the patterns of structuring that count. This is a higher level property of the system: its description requires variables that relate to more than just the properties of the components. […] In addition to the properties of the units themselves, it is the set of relations between units […] that is crucial to building up complexity. These aspects cannot be reduced to lower level variables. […] Higher level structural patterns channel causation at lower levels in the system, breaking symmetry and so constraining what happens at those levels” (Ellis 2016, pp. 85–87).

  4. 4.

    Ellis can support this type of causation with any example where the whole determines movements of and changes to its parts, like the changes in the cardiovascular system due to heavy body movements of the whole organism. This seems to suggest that for Ellis a top-cause must always be deterministic for the bottom-effect. On the question of how top-down causation and the question of indeterminism fit together, see (Beebee 2014).

  5. 5.

    Take solar system science: It studies our solar system. Modular subsystems on the same level of complexity and which causally interact with one another include the planet Earth, the moon Callisto, the dwarf planet Ceres, the Mars trojans, Halley’s Comet and many others. The causal relations form a net with an internal hierarchy (Ceres is part of the asteroid belt, moons orbit their planets, trojans are tied to their planets or moons and so on). Yet even at this one distinct level of nature, there are modular subsystems with greater complexity than others: Jupiter seems to be more complex than Halley’s Comet if we take Jupiter not only to have more functionally distinct parts (an outer and inner atmosphere with sub-parts like cloud layers, possibly a rocky core, etc. (Guillot et al. 2004)) than Halley’s Comet but also, due to the interaction of those parts, more genuine complexity, such as weather events (take the Great Red Spot). According to Ellis’s view, interaction between these two modules, Jupiter and Halley’s Comet, in the whole of the solar system still has to be conceived as same-level causation, even if there can be a difference of complexity between modules.

  6. 6.

    The option to define a natural system by way of analysing whether its complexity actually exceeds and not only equals the complexity of the sum of its real functional parts (which would supposedly be the case for any mereological sum of the complexity of arbitrary parts, say the planet Mars and the exoplanet TrES-3b regarded as one part) is not further pursued in Ellis’s work as far as I know. If this were possible it would offer a way to search for cases of strong emergence and top-down causation (understood as feedback loops).

  7. 7.

    In cell A we find a cell nucleus and in cell B we do not.

  8. 8.

    Ellis’s argument stands in a long line of antireductionist arguments that follow Anderson’s classic criticism of the constructionist hypothesis, that is “the ability to start from those [fundamental] laws and reconstruct the universe”, because “at each new level of complexity entirely new properties appear”. (Anderson 1972, p. 393) Many philosophers and scientists with the same agenda follow his lead (see Meyr 1988; Nagel 1998; Castellani 2002; Ellis 2006; Chalmers 2006; Corning 2012). Thomas Nagel’s argument against reductionism, for example, introduces levels in nature as joints in nature (Nagel 1998, pp. 7–12): Our explanations and theories always focus on a specific level, depending on which scale we are looking at. According to Nagel, not all natural kinds and laws can be defined in this reductionist way, functional properties in biology being a case in point. One consequence of his argument is that levels in nature are real because the natural kinds of the higher level of biology cannot even in principle be defined by the fundamental level of physics. So we have at least two distinct levels: The fundamental level of physics without functional properties and the higher level of biology with them. Only an ontological reductionist could claim the absence of distinct levels of nature. Nagel does not find a joint in nature which separates the level of larger entities with functional properties and the level of smaller entities without them. (Though even this is debatable; for a definition of every physical property as dispositional and second-order functional property see Yates 2012.)

  9. 9.

    It would of course be possible to consider A7*, which would not make this claim, because it neither follows from the first sentence of A7 nor does the first sentence require the second as a premise. But with the second sentence, A7 is closer to L7.

References

  • Anderson, P. W. (1972). More is different: Broken symmetries and the nature of the hierarchical structure of science. Science, 177, 393–396.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Beebee, H. (2014). Radical Indeterminism and top-down Causation. Res Philosophica, 91, 537–545.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2006). Where is the theory in our “Theories” of causality? Journal of Philosophy, 103(2), 56–66.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Cartwright, N. (2007). Hunting causes and using them. Approaches in philosophy and economics. Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Castellani, E. (2002). Reductionism, emergence, and effective field theories. Studies in History and Philosophy of Modern Physics, 33, 251–267.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Chalmers, D. (2006). Strong and weak emergence. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The Re-emergence of emergence. The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion (pp. 244–256). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Corning, P. (2012). The Re-emergence of emergence, and the Causal role of synergy in emergent evolution. Synthese, 185(2), 295–317.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • de Vreese, L. (2010). Disentangling causal pluralism. In R. Vanderbeeken & B. D’Hooghe (Eds.), Worldviews, science and Us: Studies of analytical metaphysics: A selection of topics from a methodological perspective (pp. 207–223). Singapur: World Scientific Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2006). On the nature of emergent reality. In P. Clayton & P. Davies (Eds.), The Re-emergence of emergence. The emergentist hypothesis from science to religion (pp. 79–107). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2008). On the nature of causation in complex systems. Transactions of the Royal Society of South Africa, 63, 69–84.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2009). Top-down causation and the human brain. In N. Murphy, G. F. R. Ellis, & T. O’Connor (Eds.), Downward causation and the neurobiology of free will (pp. 63–81). Berlin: Springer.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2012). Top-down causation and emergence: Some comments on mechanisms. Interface Focus, 2, 126–140.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2013). The arrow of time and the nature of spacetime. Studies in History and Philosophy of Science Part B: Modern Physics, 44, 242–262.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R. (2016). How can physics underlie the mind? Top-down causation in the human context. Berlin: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R., Auletta, G., & Jaeger, L. (2008). Top-down causation by information control: from a philosophical problem to a scientific research program. Interface, 5(27), 1159–1172.

    Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R., Noble, D., & O’Connor, T. (2012). Top-down causation: An integrating theme within and across the sciences? Interface Focus, 2, 1–3.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R., & Drossel, B. (2018). Contextual wavefunction collapse: An integrated theory of quantum measurement. New Journal of Physics, 20, 113025.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R., & Drossel, B. (2019). How downwards causation occurs in digital computers. Foundations of Physics, 49(11), 1253–1277.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Ellis, G. F. R., & Gabriel, M. (2021). Physical, logical, and mental top-down effects. In M. Gabriel & J. Voosholz (Eds.), Top-down causation and emergence (vol. 439, pp. 3–38). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C., Køppe, S., & Stjernfelt, F. (1997). Explaining emergence—Towards an ontology of levels. Journal for General Philosophy of Science, 28, 83–119.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Emmeche, C., Køppe, S., & Stjernfelt, F. (2000). Levels, emergence, and three versions of downward causation. In P. Bøgh Andersen, C. Emmeche, N. Ole Finnemann, & P. Voetmann Christiansen (Eds.), Downward causation. minds, bodies and matter (pp. 13–34). Århus: Aarhus University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Gabriel, M. (2015). Fields of sense. A new realist ontology. Edinburgh: Edinburgh University Press.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Green, S., & Batterman, R. W. (2021). Causal slack and Top.Down causation. universality and functional equivalence in physics and biology. In M. Gabriel & J. Voosholz (Eds.), Top-down causation and emergence (vol. 439, pp. 39–63). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Guillot, T., Stevenson, D. J., Hubbard, W. B., & Saumon, D. (2004). The interior of jupiter. In F. Bagenal, T. E. Dowling, & W. B. McKinnon (Eds.) Jupiter: The planet, satellites and magnetosphere (pp. 35–57). Cambridge: Cambridge University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Hulswit, M. (2005). How causal is downward causation? Zeitschrift für allgemeine Wissenschaftstheorie, 36(2), 261–287.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1992). Multiple realization and the metaphysics of reduction. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 52, 1–26.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Kim, J. (1999). Making sense of emergence. Philosophical Studies, 95, 3–36.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Liseau, R., Larsson, B., Lunttila, T., Olberg, M., Rydbeck, G., Bergman, P., et al. (2015). Gas and dust in the star-forming region ρ Oph A. The dust opacity exponent β and the gas-to-dust mass ratio g2d. A&A, 578, A313.

    Google Scholar 

  • Longworth, F. (2006). Causation, pluralism and responsibility. Philosophica, 77, 45–68.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Luu, T., Meißner, U.-G. (2021). On the topic of emergence from an effective field theory perspective. In M. Gabriel & J. Voosholz (Eds.), Top-down causation and emergence (vol. 439, pp. 101–114). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Meillassoux, Q. (2008). After finitude. An essay on the necessity of contingency. New York: Continuum.

    Book  Google Scholar 

  • Meyr, E. (1988). The limits of reductionism. Nature, 331, 475.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Nagel, T. (1998). Reductionism and antireductionism. In G. R. Bock, J. A. Goode (Eds.), The limits of reductionism (pp. 3–14). Chichster: Wiley.

    Google Scholar 

  • Paolini Paoletti, M., & Orilia, F. (2017). Downward causation: An opinionated introduction. In M. Paolini Paoletti & F. Orilia (Eds.), Philosophical and scientific perspectives on downward causation (pp. 1–21). London, New York, USA: Routledge.

    Chapter  Google Scholar 

  • Paul, L. A. (2009). Counterfactual theories. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & P. Menzies (Eds.), The Oxford handbook on causation (pp. 159–184). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H. (2017). Causation, intervention and agency—Woodward on Menzies and Price. In H. Beebee, C. Hitchcock, & H. Price (Eds.), Making a difference (pp. 73–98). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Price, H., & Menzies, P. (1993). Causation as a secondary quality. British Journal of Philosophy of Science, 44, 187–203.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Psillos, S. (2010). Causal pluralism. In R. Vanderbeeken & B. D’Hooghe (Eds.), Worldviews, science and Us: Studies of analytical metaphysics: A selection of topics from a methodological perspective (pp. 131–151). Singapur: World Scientific Publication.

    Google Scholar 

  • Siriwardena, S. (2019). Old problems for the agency theory of causal discourse. Erkenntnis, 84(4), 939–951.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2007). Essay review of Woodward, “Making Things Happen”. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 74, 233–249.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Strevens, M. (2013). Causality reunified. Erkenntnis, 78, 229–320.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Williamson, J. (2006). Causal pluralism versus epistemic causality. Philosophica, 77, 69–96.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2003). Making things happen. A theory of causal explanation. Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2007). Causation with a human face. In H. Price & R. Corry (Eds.), Causation and the constitution of reality (pp. 66–105). Oxford: Oxford University Press.

    Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2008). Response to Strevens. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 77, 193–212.

    Article  Google Scholar 

  • Woodward, J. (2021). Downward causation defended. In M. Gabriel & J. Voosholz (Eds.), s Top-down causation and emergence (vol. 439, pp. 217–251). Cham: Springer.

    Google Scholar 

  • Yates, D. (2012). The essence of dispositional essentialism. Philosophy and Phenomenological Research, 87, 93–128.

    Article  Google Scholar 

Download references

Author information

Authors and Affiliations

Authors

Corresponding author

Correspondence to Jan Voosholz .

Editor information

Editors and Affiliations

Appendix

Appendix

I would like to thank Markus Gabriel and Otávio Bueno for the encouragement and opportunity to write this paper and helpful remarks, Alex Englander and Max Kistler for their comments on an earlier version of this paper, and Noemi Stelzig for all her support during the process of writing.

Rights and permissions

Reprints and permissions

Copyright information

© 2021 Springer Nature Switzerland AG

About this chapter

Check for updates. Verify currency and authenticity via CrossMark

Cite this chapter

Voosholz, J. (2021). Top-Down Causation Without Levels. In: Voosholz, J., Gabriel, M. (eds) Top-Down Causation and Emergence. Synthese Library, vol 439. Springer, Cham. https://doi.org/10.1007/978-3-030-71899-2_11

Download citation

Publish with us

Policies and ethics